Thursday, December 3, 2009
Stuart Mill's Attempt
John Stuart Mill’s challenges the idea that in order to have more prosperity and welfare, resources need to be overly used to ensure economic growth. Conversely, he believes that constraints on our over consumptive attitudes is needed in order to improve the quality of life. Ultimately, Mill is arguing for a more qualitative way of live as opposed to a quantitative. He states that the increase of wealth is not boundless, and that the progressive state will one day come to a halt. The only logical conclusion is that this unlimited growth attitude will destroy the environment and inevitably reduced quality of life. However, he seems to write as though he knows we will always move forward, and will not heed the warning signs the environment throws our way. This article was written in 1884. We have, to this day, not slowed down. In fact, humanity is moving ever forward. Every year the Earth is pumped with more gases due to the anthropogenic caused by mankind.
Another thing I picked up on was his common idea of integrating humanity and the universe. He groups everyone and everything together as a species in which needs to work together to improve the overall universe. He pushes for education to be a main concern. It’s as if being less educated is a scape-goat, exemption from the overall economic crisis. Therefore we should include them. The “better” minds are those who are going to bring this universe to a standstill, but it will affect everyone inside it. Overall, people should take responsibility for their actions, and in the meantime cease the notion that economic growth comes from killing the Earth.
Unfortunately, it is past this point at which I became stuck. In describing the limitations of CBA, Schmidtz emphasizes the importance in respecting people’s rights, certainly an important and admirable action. However, to illustrate his argument, he introduces Peeveyhouse v. Garland Coal (1962). He notes that Garland Coal refused to perform its contractual obligations in their entirety by not restoring the Peeveyhouse property back to its original condition after completing a strip-mining operation on it. Restoring the land would cost Garland Coal $29,000, while the restored land’s value would have be worth only $300. Referring to the Supreme Court of Oklahoma’s decision to award Peeveyhouse $300 in damages as “generally…regarded as utterly mistaken,” Schmidtz explains that the court reached its decision because the restoration would not be cost-effective. Though quite biased, nothing Schmidtz stated was false. Still, I feel need to offer defense to the court’s decision. To do so, I used the case law - http://academic.udayton.edu/CasesLawEcon/Contracts/Peevyhouse%201962.pdf.
One aspect ignored by Schmidtz was the actual contract itself. In exchange for royalties on the extracted coal, Peeveyhouse allowed Garland to strip-mine a section of their land for five years. A provision of this contract was that Garland was expected to return the land to its original condition. Although the major terms of the contract were upheld by both parties, Garland did breach the contract by not performing the provision. However, there was substantial performance of the contract. Although it can be argued that $300 in expectancy damages (the value of the land had Garland restored it) was not sufficient, it is also not unreasonable to argue that $300 is an equitable remedy. For instance, the economic waste doctrine holds that “if granting repair costs to the owner would result in ‘unreasonable economic waste,’ then the proper measure of the owner's damages should be the difference between the value of the project as promised in the contract and its value as delivered” (https://litigation-essentials.lexisnexis.com/webcd/app?action=DocumentDisplay&crawlid=1&doctype=cite&docid=43+DePaul+L.+Rev.+185&srctype=smi&srcid=3B15&key=5c38a755056f84a867ca8216380126c8). As a main rule of contract law, a party should not be awarded more damages than she would have anticipated had the contract she was a party to had it not been breached. In an ideal world, Garland would owe Peeveyhouse specific performance, or at least enough compensation for Peeveyhouse to find an outside party to hire to fix his land. In such an ideal world, the court would consider the subjective value of the land to Peeveyhouse, and not just its monetary value. But, such a thing as expectancy damages is necessary in the realm of contracts.
As discussed in my business law class, consider my making a contract with a builder to build my dream home. I stipulate a specific placement of the windows in my house. Upon completion of my home, I see that my windows are placed in wrong positions by a matter of inches. The builder did in fact breach our contract, and I want him to correct his mistake, which would indeed involve a great sum of money and seems on the whole, an unreasonable remedy for the builder’s innocent mistake. Protecting the builder from such a commercial impracticality, the court would consider any loss of value to my home due to the different placement of the windows. Although the placement has important subjective value to me, it would not change the monetary amount my home is worth. As such, no action would be taken against the builder.
This tangent was probably not worthwhile, in that I still find myself agreeing with Schmidtz’s core points. Maybe it could illustrate the complexity behind decisions and policies in that cost-effectiveness must at least be a consideration in addition to morality. But overall, I just found myself irked at Schmidtz’s quick dismissal and simplification of the Oklahoma court’s conclusion.
Citizens or Consumers?:
I agree with Sagoff’s argument for a Kantian approach to policy recommendation in regard to the environment – humans ultimately have to be treated as “ends in themselves” and not as simply a set of market preferences. It is obvious, however, that what people politically support and what people consume can be completely different and, in fact, contradictory. Our market preferences will never completely align with our political preferences, but this doesn’t mean that we should view human beings as merely “haver[s] of wants” (635) but rather it suggests that our market preferences ultimately cannot be the judge of our policy, especially in regard to the environment. The economist approach to policy formation suggests that what we ought to do as a community is less important than what we actually do as individuals making choices in the market place. Morality, however, isn’t concerned necessarily with the way things are but rather with the way things should be, and indeed, the economist’s position then isn’t concerned with morality but with efficiency and expediency in the market.
The challenge which Sargoff faces, however, is the practical application of the Kantian position. If, as the economist suggest, our market preferences accurately reflect our interests – though we would support just political causes at the same time – then ultimately our policy must coincide with the majority opinion. We can’t pretend that we are against factory farming if we are consistently supporting the industry; our market preferences show to the economists our true selves behind the politically correct/ideal mask which we hide behind. Sargoff, however, responds to this objection by claiming that, though our market preferences as consumers may ultimately express our true interests, we are nevertheless still outside of morality, that is, still talking about the way things are rather than how they ought to be. The practical application of Kantian principles, while extremely demanding, may be exactly what morality requires and our obligations as citizens may, in fact, sometimes trump our preferences as individual consumers.
Wednesday, December 2, 2009
Schmidtz
Schmidtz’s piece is one of the few readings we have had that seems to takes other arguments more seriously, and understands that things are not simply black and white. His support of Cost Benefit Analysis is well placed, as is his skepticism in it. Though I agree that there are benefits from CBA Full Cost Accounting, such as the public’s ability to scrutinize and provide input in, Schmidtz does not address the issue of value enough. To be clear though, CBA, if done properly, does offer a chance for greater equity, environmental protection, and other goods. To denounce CBA in every aspect implies turning a blind eye to another tool that may help people makes good decisions (not a definite), something that makes no sense.
The other issue I have with CBA concerns values. Schmidtz makes reference to this, but he does not seem to give the idea enough weight. He falls back on the fact that we are simply human on several occasions. We are not evil, just human. Does that imply we naturally do not act fully accountable? If that’s the case then there is a great deal of work ahead of humanity.
I got a bit side tracked, but another point I wanted to mention regards the case of the neighbor with the barking dog. It says he’s not evil for keeping his neighbors up at night, since he was not fully accountable. In this case, and many others though, I believe he (or a she) is fully accountable though. The point here is that the others do not react when they have the ability to do so. One last thing to mention is the use of the Ontario Hydro case. Schmidtz final mentioning of this is that the prospects of public accounting made Ontario Hydro rethink what they owe the environment. There could be a multitude of other reasons this happened that Schmidtz does not mention, ranging from tax breaks, a new CEO, new legislation, a bad series of PR, and more. Schmidtz should not presume so much.
this post has no title
Cost-Benefit Analysis and Decision Making
If the potential costs or disadvantages of injecting sulphate aerosols into the atmosphere (e.g., causing further anthropogenic harm to the atmosphere/ozone, causing harm/injury to people, causing species extinctions) outweigh the potential benefits of doing so (e.g., improving the condition of the atmosphere), the logical conclusion that we would then come to would be that we should not use this method of geoengineering because of the risk(s) associated with it. However, any decision, whether or not it concerns the environment, should be made based on the consideration of multiple factors- cost-benefit analysis could be one of these factors but should not be the only one. Likewise, any other factor should not on its own be the basis of any decisions, especially those decisions that directly concern the health of the environment.
In Defense of Steady-State Economics
In realizing our current condition with overcrowding, struggle for employment, depletion of natural resources, and extremities between classes, Mill states that a steady-state would be an improvement. Being in a more stagnant system does not mean there will not be continued increase in spiritual, educational, technological, and scientific fields. And it could increase these parts of culture and social progress as a whole.
Mill offers a few options for steps to reaching a steady-state. He mentions stricter population control (and distribution) and legislation that leads to restraints on sum/acquisition of fortune one may have-leading to better paid and overall wealthier population of workers.
I feel, however, more information is necessary in this excerpt concerning the process of reaching a steady-state economy from our current status. How exactly is population going to be controlled so that it reaches a state closer to the birth rate mirroring the death rate? There should also be more mentioned about the policies or steps for controlling our consumption (of energy and materials). There should be a focus on planning out and setting aside enough land and water so that ecological processes may continue with little/less disturbance to maintain a balance between human presence and natural ecosystems and species. Increased regulations on rates and amount of resource use is also necessary in addition to higher/stricter standards for emission (limits) and toxicity (severance taxes, quotas for extraction...).
Finally, a statement Mill makes on page 601 should be treated more as a matter of opinion rather than fact, and may not be the best support for the notion that steady-state will work. Mill claims, "the best state for human nature is that in which, while no one is poor, no one desires to be richer, nor has any reason to fear being thrust back, by the efforts of others to push themselves forward", yet where is the evidence that this is fact? For throughout history, I personally only am familiar with constant states of competition, of bettering oneself or one's clan/group. Biologically, I feel that his statement lacks support, for every species strives to continually evolve to a more "fit" state. Such a Utopian world he describes doesn't appear to have ever existed (or consequently prove it works/is feasible) and seems will be an extremely difficult status to attain based off of (evolutionary) history.
100+ years later, we're still not there. Why?
We cannot continue to obey the commands of comparative advantage and accumulation. To do so is to delay the inevitable achievement of stasis, jeopardizing the environment and human well-being.
I think Sagoff can use Mill's concept to further explain why somethings are - and should remain- outside the control of the market, owing to their super-economic value (i.e. have moral or aesthetic value beyond that for which we are willing to pay.) The economic valuation of things, exemplified by the application of cost-benefit analysis and the commodification of the environment or worker safety, is a driving force in our refusal to accept a stationary state.
Sagoff
I felt that Sagoff’s critique of the cost-benefit analysis adequately displayed the problems in using such a system. How could a person’s life, or even their safety for that matter, ever be treated as a commodity and therefore given an exact monetary value? Coinciding with Sagoff, I believe that one’s life cannot be accounted for in this manner and that human life, as well as environmental quality has a greater, inherent value. Given this, I did find the first few sections of the article to be a bit overwhelming; however they did continue to illustrate his Kantian viewpoint.
With that aside, I had a question of whether or not this Kantian value system was one that Sagoff thought could be implemented practically. He describes the system as needing individuals to “put aside their personal interests, it would follow that they put aside their power as well.” (p.627) However, isn’t he advocating that this value or practice of neutral positioning be instilled in the individual, since there would be no way to enforce it? How could we force individuals in power to accept this Kantian view in order to find a neutral position from which to judge? Also, if this system were accepted, what would happen in situations where there are opposed sides, each with their own legitimate claims? I understand that this may be delving too much into the practicality of the issue but it just arose as I finished reading the piece.
Overall Sagoff clearly displays the problem with the cost-benefit value system in today’s society and does a good job of calling for a replacement using the Kantian value system. I felt a personal agreement with the aim of a society where the individual is valued for himself and the population disregards making decisions in a cost-benefit manner because it ensures that there is never an acceptable amount of personal suffering. Also, he does an excellent job of calling to the individual to realize the power they possess in their actions and use it to benefit others not just look in self-interest.
Quality not quantity: High densities promote the spread of infectious diseases
Thoughts on Sagoff's Message
Redistribution is the best bet in my eyes.
Cost-Benefit Doesn't Cut it
I am in agreement with Sagoff that economic factors should not be the only concern especially when dealing with things in which the value cannot be determined by how much one is willing to pay for it. For example some believe that steps should be taken to protect worker only insofar as the benefits outweigh the costs. This is speaking in market terms. When protection becomes too expensive, the cost is no longer worth it to some people. However, the cost of these safety measures is too limited of an analysis of if they are worth employing. While society may get more "bang for its buck" this way, it is at the expense of the safety of the workers. To not take the proper measures to protect these people is immoral. This ethical dilemma according to Sagoff outweighs any monetary costs that will result.
Similarly, in the case of the environment, one cannot put a price on the trees, the land, and the creatures that inhabit them. While one cannot give a monetary value to the environment, many still argue never the less, that it has substantial value. Sagoff argues that there are two sides to every person: the consumer, who only looks for what he or she wants or needs, and the citizen, who makes decisions based on what is best for not only themselves but the population as a whole. The cost-benefit analysis only takes into account how much someone will pay for something. People are only viewed as consumers. We tend to only our wants and desires.
Sagoff points out that we also act as citizens and that this causes us to act to maintain the balance of a "good" society. Cost-benefit analysis is a good place to start when dealing with things such as public safety and environmental quality, but we must not stop at how much people want something and how much it will cost us. We need to look further into the moral implications that the decisions incur. Just because something is economically more cost effective, doesn't make it right.
Sagoff
I agree with him that a big problem is the fact that individuals don't realize the influence they have. They are not lost in the multitude. I remember I confronted a friend of mine recently for not recycling some bottles and such and she said something along the lines of "It's not like it makes a difference. I'm just one person". She didnt understand that it is individuals who lead to a multitude. It has to start with someone before it can become many. People need to face the fact that they can't be lazy and say they don't matter because they are only one person. It will take this recognition on people's part before the proper changes can be met.
He reminds us that we prevent significant deterioration of air quality as a matter of self interest and as a matter of collective self respect for everyone and our planet. This is the compromise, the balance that is needed between the two types of interests. The answer involves, in part, a recognition of responsiblities both from us and from the government. As humans, we must address our contempt for the contradictional lifestyle we embrace, we must step out of our habitual tendencies and up to the plate that has a time limit, which people are just starting to understand.
Tuesday, December 1, 2009
Monday, November 30, 2009
Geoengineering
sophie's choice comparison
I wholeheartedly believe most of Gardiner’s piece in terms of our blindness to the underlying problem and our arrogance to think we can control the Earth; however, there is one point in his paper that deducts from his overall argument. He details additional liabilities and marring evils to geoengineering. He makes the point that he agrees that we have a moral responsibility to future generations with geoengineering but that we also have a moral responsibility to pursue better climate policies. This is an example of Sophie’s Choice. He discusses Sophie’s Choice as an illustration that can be applied to the geoengineering debate. Sophie had a choice; one or the other. She had to choose between saving one of her children or submitting both to be killed by the Nazis. There was no in between. She made a clear choice in a black and white decision. However, in the geoengineering debate there is plenty of gray area, which makes this a poor reference and argument that deducts from Gardiner’s argument.
Geoengineering is not something that we have to do cold turkey. Why are we suggesting that it is one or the other? To do it or not? Sophie’s Choice is not a good comparison as it was only a decision with two choices. Crutzen favored exploring the possibility of geoengineering with sulfate aerosols. Therefore, with more research of geoengineering, there could be many ways in which we pursue this option so its not a do it or not solution.
Because climate change is a complex and intricate problem, there is no black and white. Thus, it might be our best option to benefit ourselves from technical fixes, like geoengineering, in the transition for a change to even occur. Why can’t we at least investigate whether geoengineering could be one of those fixes? Geoengineering might have the potential to be a good way to bring rising temperatures under short-term control and it could also allow us to wait for the longer-term fix of cutting carbon emissions. Here is a gray area that is unlike Sophie’s Choice in terms of being one or the other. Therefore, it seems as though we have a moral obligation, one that is very different from Sophie, to consider geoengineering through more research so to better understand the gray area.
When Gardiner criticizes the suggestions of Ralph Cicerone concerning geoengenering, he paraphrases Cicerone’s argument to a level where it is easy to find vague and often insufficient arguments. The first aspect of Cicerones’ position that Gardiner contends is the desire to promote free inquiry in the research of geoengering. Gardiner suggests that Cicerone is considering freedom of inquiry in fantastic terms. Gardiner uses the example of counting every blade of grass on the lawn of someone in Washington just to know, for the value that simple knowledge of how many blades of grass exist in this lawn. While I am not sure the exact position of Cicerone, it is reasonable to assume that his argument for open inquiry is meant to entail at least some degree of triage. Yet Gardiner suggests that knowledge associated with geoengenering research may be irrelevant. Citing Thomas Schelling, Gardiner says that inquiry and research may prove to be irrelevant due to the expectation that technological advancements in the future will be so profound it will negate the relevance of the geoengenering research done in the present. I take this claim by Gardiner presumptuous and ill-conceived. To assume that there will be these technological advancements in the future is naïve, not to mention the assumption that present research will not at least hasten these significant technological advancements is pessimistic and reliant on the future for answers. Therefore, while I agree that some knowledge is trivial in researching geoengenering, you can’t assume that all research is so futile.
Secondly, I find the argument concerning the degree of resource expenditure on geoengenering to be insufficient. While Gardiner admits that geoengenering research is not an “all or nothing game”, he is suggesting that there is no way to adequately or prudently allocate funding or research without it becoming just that. Implicit within his argument is the contention that we are unable to rationally begin research on geoengenering without detrimentally underfunding other more important projects. I agree this is a cause for concern and that there will be difficult choices made, but this does not justify not taking the chance to do this research. Gardiner seems to take a pessimistic view of geoengering research, and ultimately finds that it’s deployment is a question concerning the lesser of two evils, but it seems he places much of his faith on the science of the future. I find this to be ill conceived because if it comes down to future generations inheriting the precedent we set with regards to geoenegering research, they will leave it to the next generation as well. Personally, why not take the chance now? There may be unforeseen goods rather than evils that come from research.
Geoengineering = Open-Heart Surgery?
This analogy does not fit climate change and geoengineering completely (Ex. It does not fully consider the intergenerational dilemma by having only one human body), but I am interested in its implications. Political inertia is similar to the resistance one has to changing their diet because both are a result of conflicting values. While the body desires fats, salts, and sugars in large quantities, the mind can also realize the negative effects of such high consumption. Similarly, “we” can see the theoretical implications of our consumption of fossil fuels and the resultant emissions, but that comes into conflict with our “high-consumption” way-of-life. We can rely on medicine or geoengineering to bail us out of the “bad diet” but is that sustainable? However we could take the rout e of geoengineering being a bridge between our bad life-style and our “good” life-style afterwards. After a quick search on Google, I found this quote from someone who has worked with people on changing their diets, “In 20 years of working with patients, I've found that people will commit to change only when their motivation outweighs the challenges,” (oprah.com). It seems that there is a consensus that mitigation is the best solution but a lack of sufficient reasons to make it a reality.
“Calculated moral failure”: Accounting for the moral failings of others
Consider how the advocates of geoengineering projects are not necessarily the same individuals responsible for excessive carbon emissions and for climate change. In this way, while the decision to begin geoengineering research in preparation for a future scenario where it might be necessary is a “calculated moral failure”, it is not necessarily the moral failure of the person doing the calculating. Instead, it might be calculated by geoengineers on behalf of the irresponsible citizens of the world. If the motivation to pursue geoengineering lies in the expectation of the continued moral failings of others, I think this is justified.
Of course, as Gardiner acknowledges, the options of reducing our carbon emissions and beginning geoengineering research are not mutually exclusive; while it is uncertain to what degree we should pursue each of these, we should probably do both. So, if we genuinely try to decrease our carbon emissions and at the same time begin geoengineering research, knowing it might necessary because of others’ failure to reduce their own emissions, this can hardly be thought of as a moral failure. Indeed, it might be said that we should try harder to get others to reduce emissions, but we will only achieve so much success at this, and at a certain point it becomes a better use of time to in some capacity pursue geoengineering.
Let’s reconsider who is morally at fault. So, while Gardiner considers the pursuit of geoengineering research to be the acknowledgement of a moral failure, we might respond by saying that if one does not advocate the taking of precautionary measures, keeping in mind the inevitable proportion of the population that does not adopt a more responsible lifestyle (such precautionary measures might be advocating geoengineering research), that is also a moral failure. Again, while beginning geoengineering research is acknowledging a moral failure, it is not necessarily our failure. Furthermore, we might actually be obligated to do such research.