Thursday, November 12, 2009
Separator post
Singer and Mason’s Anthropocentric Arguments
We will begin by considering how one might be unconvinced by the authors’ arguments relating to animal suffering. While much of what is written in the book is simple documentation of how animals are treated, there are also controversial claims made, such as those stating that animals “enjoy” things. Such claims, while not plainly wrong, are definitely controversial.
Even a sentience based theorist such as Peter Singer admits of some gray areas relating to which animals can and cannot, and when animals do and do not, suffer. The authors feel that in such unclear cases “if there is uncertainty about whether what we do will cause serious harm, we should give the benefit of the doubt to the being whom we might harm” (133). This is a possible course of action, but of course we must acknowledge the general fact that in all probability, some individuals will not be seduced by the charm of this principle. Following the question of which animals can feel pain, there are the further difficult questions of how great animal suffering is, how cognitively rich it is (if they can experience something like ‘mental anguish’) and finally, whether this suffering is morally relevant. So, generally speaking, the authors have a lot of work to do to convince their opponents that the animals themselves are wronged.
We will now consider some of their anthropocentric arguments. The authors argue that factory farming negatively affects humans in the form of ‘hidden costs’. Concerning shrimp farming in India, the authors write, “for every rupee the economy gained by shrimp farming, local communities lost at least two, and in some regions, four, through damage to fishing and other resources” (127). This is not special to fish, as factory farms on land have similarly negative impact on their communities. Because the landscape is degraded by millions of pounds of animal waste which comes from factory farms, people in the communities must ultimately pay for this, effectively subsidizing the ‘cheap cost of food’. Similarly, tax money goes to families of farm employees who live below the poverty line because of their low salaries. So, while factory farmed food seems to be cheap, this is made up for in other ways.
Another one of the authors’ primary concerns is the massive amounts of food which are fed to factory farmed animals, and the amount of energy which is required to produce this food. That is to say, we are feeding factory farmed animals such as chicken, fish, pigs and cows substantially more food than they will yield in meat (simply because we like the way they taste). This is a potential anthropocentric argument because, to speak crudely, if we did not have factory farms, we could instead use these crops to feed starving people of the world. Consider the way in which this argument, like the above one, only concern human well being.
Our fear is that these extremely convincing anthropocentric arguments might be obscured by a reader’s disagreement with the arguments from animal suffering. Of course we acknowledge that this would be no fault of the authors. We do not here object to their argument but instead wish to simply advance their anthropocentric arguments independently, as a means of addressing an audience which might possibly be concerned with these issues alone. Furthermore, we find the resulting argument to be convincing.
Food Choices, Political Action, and Class
Judy Wicks, owner of the White Dog Café in Philadelphia, writes on her menu that “eating is a political act” and also “likens food choices to voting for a better farm and food policy” (173). I agree with this point – and I really like the idea that our food choices should be understood as an empowering action made by informed citizens – however, I think that there is an objection to this model that isn’t discussed enough, namely how class determines whether the political nature of our food choices has any weight. Food choices are ultimately economic choices; when we spend money on certain foods we are supporting specific markets with their own set of values. At the same time, however, our food choices are sometimes restricted by our economic means. Some markets, like fast food chains, support factory farming, while others like the White Dog Café support local, fair trade, and organic products. But when one equates food choices (and by extension economic choices) to voting power, an undemocratic system emerges. If, in a local economy, there are considerable amounts of people who are morally opposed to factory farming but aren’t wealthy, and at the same time there is a smaller but much more affluent group of people who aren’t concerned with animal welfare, the significance of food choice as a political act seems mitigated. Easily, the wealthier people could continue to flood globalized, corporate, or factory farming markets with money while the less affluent members of the society are left fighting an uphill battle – the wealthy in this scenario get more votes. If we are to consider eating as a political and economic act, ultimately those who have more economic power are the ones defining the market and political system. It’s also plausible that many people will buy fast food because it’s cheaper even if they don’t ethically agree with factory farming. Again, in this scenario economic power defines the food choices we can and cannot make, and thus the food-choices-as-voting-power model is, in the end, undemocratic. I’m intending to argue that making strategic food choices is an ineffective political move, but only that it’s restricted by class and that reliance on free market capitalism and supply-demand models are not the best way to create political change.
Wednesday, November 11, 2009
I agree that it is morally wrong to consume food that is produced in a manner that is harmful to animals, especially if a person is aware of the circumstances under which these animals live. This second family they do a case study of does a pretty good job in my opinion; they aren’t perfect, but they do well as far as food choices, especially for both having full time jobs and children. I guess in the authors’ opinion that isn’t an excuse, which makes some sense. However, I don’t see how the average person would have the time or the means to find out where all their food comes from, find out the organic/sustainable options in their area, weigh those options against each other (based on travel, growth methods, working conditions, etc), and end up making the correct decision. It’s a difficult endeavor that’s at odds with the system, which obviously doesn’t make it excusable, but I’m just unsure how a person would ever know if they’re making the right choices.
Issues with Cod, Commons, and More.
For the most part Singer and Mason seem to have decided eating locally is a poor idea. They shoot down the ethical arguments for eating locally provided by FoodRoute, with the exception of the part where you'll support endangered family farms. However, even here they seem to offer little backing besides the fact that one will lose some rural values. To counter this though, why not say that through this changing of the way our society is structured we are creating new values. Values come and go, as do the ways in which societies function. It is good not to forget about our roots, but if we want to really address the problems facing us because of big non-family farms we should first devote ourselves to it, so we can then move on from it. Instead of resisting progress and holding onto traditions we should be moving forward. There are obviously costs that come with progress like this, but a way to combat this problem is not to hold onto to outdated forms of farming that if we returned to would only lessen the amount of food in the world (thus heightening the cost from lack of supplies and inefficiency in production relative to a larger farm).
With this in mind they offer no real ethical incentive to support local farming. Another gripe I had with Singer and Mason is there occasionally use of statistics and facts. Though all I do not doubt are true, many times they seem only used to create a sense of urgency or fear in the reader. Other occasions such as the case of the Pollock fisheries ends up having no real weight to their argument. They list huge statistics but fail to actually explain the ill effects on the environment or fish (other than being eaten).
Finally a quick point I want to mention is how willing they adhere to the tragedy of the commons. They let it slide by without much of a defense and leave the reader to assume they must be right and all will starve. This has never really happened though. People are not stupid enough to do so, and on the occasions where it almost happens a person/group takes control through whatever means necessary. With fisheries there has been less of a sense of urgency because of the massive amount of commons. Eventually, people will recognize something must be done, and this will happen before humanity runs out of sea food.
Downfall of the Free Market and the Collision of Animal Rights and Human Rights
Another way in which the ethics of what we eat becomes confused is with the working families. The book makes it very apparent how differently fisherman and environmental groups view what is going on in the environment. Is it right to deny a family what has been their livelihood for a very long time? I think to the average person it seems sad to destroy that historical family fisherman; however at the same time it seems like sometimes it is necessary in order to save wildlife populations. It seems hard to distinguish where the line is between animal rights and human rights. Currently it seems if humans don’t intervene and stop overfishing and over pollution of the waterways nobody will be able to enjoy the bounty of the wild however it seems hard to decide who should be able to make such decisions.
organic farming the end of the road?
Organic farmers have taken the food industry to the next level. These farmers respect the land by enhancing soil structures and conserving water. This then helps to mitigate climate change.Organic farming takes an environmental ethic and takes low-intensity farming one step further by eliminating the use of chemical fertilizers, pesticides and genetically modified organisms.
However, my one criticism is how Singer and Mason put the organic food industry on a pedestal. If the food industry, what we eat and the claim that our food choices actually really do matter, then why don’t we include other regulations on organic farming? Why not go full force? Because it’s not just food that impacts climate change, but a whole connection of differing forms of exploitation. So instead of putting the organic food industry on a pedestal, why couldn’t we raise the question of pushing the envelope even further in regards to regulations of organic agriculture? Shouldn’t tractors in organic farming have to or be required to run on biodiesel? Or even the trucks that then deliver the organic foods to stores? Singer and Mason seem to think that the organic farming industry is the solution and we are done. However, why shouldn’t their regulations be stricter too? If we really want to make an impact, then why not go all out? Why stop where we are? Organic farming is just a catalyst for more improvement in terms of sustainable and ethically ways of living.
conscientious omnivore
The parents recognize a number of factors that affect their diets...including price, time, easiness (in preparation), and what their children like. I find these to be typical of the general population, but these obstacles don't keep this family from becoming more familiar with the food industry and the products put out on the market.
In a Utopian world, Jim's diet would be most favorable for all (environment, animals, humans...) but we will never find ourselves in such a condition. A combination of vegetarians and conscientious omnivores seems a more attainable combination for society. A shift towards self-education on the consumers-part needs to be pushed. This curiosity in food production should also be geared towards the youth; starting young with kids on what foods are good, and how theses products actually get to the kitchen table will carry on with them throughout their lives.
And there seems to be a number of reasons that will work for people to be more conscientious in their purchases...like the environmental impact of farms (runoff), the amount of grains used (and wasted) for feed (for animals that don't naturally consume grain), the poor treatment of the animals (while alive and in slaughtering process), the potential health risks for humans consuming animals and their products (antibiotics, diseases, hormones...), and the differences in quality/taste of the products. Perhaps it will be like Mary Ann says, "as more consumers get aware, they make demands and create new markets"..."[and] little by little there are more food choices available and affordable" (Singer, 91).
Buying Far-Awayally Won't Cure Poverty.
The authors allude to the idea of commodity chains, which link the purchase of a final product by a consumer through each individual that had any sort of role in its production, all the way back to (in the case of food) the farmer. The trouble I have with buying non-locally (far-awayally?) is that these commodities tend to have the longest commodity chains. The further away a product originates, the more people have opportunities to dip their hands into the pot. Buying directly from the people who produce your goods is ethical because it ensures that they make a fair profit and prevents others from taking advantage of the production. While it could be argued that longer commodity chains create more jobs, an ethical goal, the possibility of buying directly proves that those jobs are unnecessary to the creation of that product and thus should not be rewarded. If local products and imported products cost the same, more of the purchase price is being redirected away from farmers to unnecessary middlemen.
I also argue that buying far-awayally doesn't really do much to cure poverty. While it might bandage it a bit for individuals who have managed to get themselves into a position where they can produce for export, the systemic causes of poverty go much deeper than Singer and Mason allow. These farmers aren't poor because not enough people are buying their goods: they're poor because our economic structures make them that way. Yes, the two cents the farmer in Kenya earns from my purchase helps, but if it weren't for all the middlemen in the commodity chain, he could be making close to the dollar that the local farmer might. In this sense, buying far-awayally supports the transnational corporations that continue to glean their money away from farmers by connecting us to far-away producers.
(Buying far-awayally and fair trade might be a solution to this.)
I believe there is a real important lesson to be learned from the portion of book concerning "If consumer demands change, then the business will change to please them". This seems really important to me. What needs changing is the business itself, and the way it does things. But the business won't change until the source of its revenue forces it to change. They will do whatever it takes to get our money. If we decide we want the cruelty to stop and refuse to buy their food that does not comply to this anti-cruetly (environment harming)method then they will not get business and will fail as a business. Its on the consumers to start the change. The problem is, enough consumers have to contribute to the cause for it to have an effect. 10% of the population isnt enough because 90% are giving them the current business under the wrong policies and standards and they care about the majority.
On page 133 there is a reference to giving animals the "benefit of the doubt" when it comes to pain and suffering. The story about the chicken being put in boiling water (unstunned) came out mutilated from its own effort to escape (broken bones and such). Some call this responsive/reflexive efforts to stimuli, and say it is not proof of suffering or cognitive response. But doesnt this intense effort on the part of the chicken to escape a seemingly painful situation earm it the "benefit of the doubt"? What exactly is it that people require in the way of seeming pain to consider giving animals the benefit of the doubt without the proof? What does it take for people to care and consider the repercussions of their choices and desires?
the facts arent enough
Environmental Concerns of Eating Meat
This does not mean that we have to stop eating meat entirely. We instead need to find better ways to maintain the animals used for consumption. Using natural food sources instead of artificial ones would be much kinder to the environment and to other people. If cows were allowed to graze normally instead of being fed unnatural corn, that corn could instead be used to feed people or the space used to grow the corn could be used to grow other types of food.
In regard to the waste produced by the animals, new techniques need to be used to dispose of it. Ideally, the waste would be subjected to some sort of treatment to remove excess nutrients that would disrupt the environment as is done with human waste. Doing this could prove to be costly, but there is one method that would work effectively without being being too time consuming or costly. The waste could be pumped back into the ground in a location that would naturally filter the waste as it worked its way through the different layers of soil. Microorganism's found naturally in the soil will break down the waste and use up the excess nutrients similar to the process used by many house-hold septic systems. This is an example of how working with nature rather than against it as we all too often do can be used to benefit us and the environment simultaneously.
Tuesday, November 10, 2009
Separator post
Monday, November 9, 2009
The main problems, then, are how to alter an entire country’s diet so that less meat is eaten, and how to alter the production of meat so that it is less damaging to the environment, animals and humans. These two dilemmas are interrelated – consumer demand drives the factory farms’ desire for increased productivity.
As Singer and Mason have repeatedly acknowledged, increased productivity usually leads towards increasingly unsafe measures within factory farms. Factory farms avoid allowing the animals “amenities” (for instance, shade in 90 degree weather, euthanizing downed animals, anesthetic before painful operations, more effective stunning before being killed) in order to preserve themselves against competing factory farms. In this way, quantity of the meat consumed (and I suppose also quality of the meat’s taste – consider the purpose of malnourishment for making “tasty” veal) is more important than the quality (ethical treatment of animals, proper disposal of waste) of factory farms.
In order to change this, consumers must demand for better quality of factory farms, even if this does mean an increase in food prices and a lesser abundance of meat. Singer and mason realized that “the system seems to recognize animal suffering only when it interferes with profitability” (54). Pressuring for better life conditions for animals with factory farms, society could make it such that profitability of a company’s animal products depends upon their just treatment of animals. We need to ask ourselves why this demand is not more prevalent in society. One reply may be that consumers are not informed about the effects of factory farming. This is indeed extremely true. Singer and Mason acknowledge that factory farms are “invisible to the public” (47). It was at this point they compared factory farming cruelty to zoo cruelty. While I agree that “public disapproval helped persuade” zoos to rectify these cruelties, I think there are some fundamental differences between zoo cruelty and factory farm cruelty which will hinder the efforts to rectify factory farm cruelties. People go to zoos to look at animals. A pleasant zoo experience involves people enjoying what they are seeing, and most people do not enjoy looking at beings suffer. It seems obvious that people would complain and express public disapproval, because they are not reaping enjoyment from the animals’ suffering. On the other hand, a pleasant meat-eating experience is gustatory in nature, during which people enjoy the meat they are consuming. The animal cruelty and environmental detriment necessary to create meat does not affect the tastiness of the meat. Should someone be informed about factory farms and upset enough to consider the experience of eating meat ruined, I should hope that they become vegetarian! But the majority of meat eaters either is fully informed as to the nature of factory farms and just does not care, or chooses to make animals invisible so that guilt will not affect the enjoyment of a tasty meaty meal.
Overall, I am still left wondering what will inspire the masses to act against factory farms. Despite some opinions to the contrary from others in class, however, I do think that it is possible to create great strides for better conditions of factory farms. Extreme measures are not necessary for this to happen (ie. that everyone must become a vegetarian), but as Spira noted, “If McDonalds moves a millimeter, everyone else will move with them” (70). Perhaps Halverson is right, and not much will be gained by making minor improvements in a “fundamentally bad system” (72), but given the present state of America’s dependence on factory farms, I think this is our only option.
This, I think, is the major dilemma. They go on to talk about major corporations like the fast food industries that took steps to make their businesses and the food that they sell more environmentally sound. However, these steps are small, and although they are on a large scale, they may not be enough. The real changes that have to happen are large changes happening on large scales, changes happening in the way McDonalds and Wal-Mart buy their food. These changes, unfortunately, do not seem to be likely to happen.
These large scale changes would mean that they would have to implement severe changes in the way that animals are treated and slaughtered. This would not only mean that the prices would go up on meat sales. This would then mean that the basic idea of both of these corporations would be in danger. There would be no more ‘Dollar Menu’ not more ‘Every Day Low Prices’. Neither of these institutions is going to risk profits for animal welfare, unless the government declares it illegal first. While the idea of these corporations being pressured by civilians and then forcing change onto farmers seems like a way to avoid the government getting involved it does not seem like it is the true fix, just a band-aid.
Ethical Intervention
Education is the staple
I already knew that big meat factories produce a lot of runoff which in turn creates Eutrophication, pollution of streams, illness to locals, a whole lot of animal cruelty, etc.. I have already had my world shattered when I read ‘Fast Food Nation’ and already know how egg, cow, pig, and chicken industries get to their final product. Along the lines however I, and society, become sheltered from the process and how rapidly these millions of animals are dying. Not until I read the exact statistics and quantitative data was I completely in shock. Anything from stating the number of turkey’s that are inseminated, which is one every 12 seconds, to the fact that the natural lifespan of a cow is around 20 years, but are usually killed at five years of age. Once the statistics are on the table is when I truly feel the affect. I do believe education is the “best defense against the animal rights attack on the… industry (pg. 47).” Education is the staple in reducing animal cruelty. The reason I say reducing is because no one will ever be willing to give it up entirely. It is a convenience for the public, and no matter what is said and shown to shut this down, the number of people willing to purchase these products overpowers the morality of the situation. For instance, I read the part about the Turkey’s and literally felt like I was reading about something getting sexually abused. However, I finished my reading, went to dinner and got a turkey burger. Awareness is important and can certainly have impact on the nation and these industries. Not only the industry but the nation should be conscious of where the food is coming from and how they are extracting it. McDonalds, which was hard for me to believe, have cleaned up their act. Not as much as I would like, but changes have been made. For instance, McDonalds has funded research aimed specifically at animal welfare and devising farming methods which offer better animal welfare. Without such activism people forget these animals are alive. I would love to be as far along as Europe seems to be, but we are where we are. At this point, the only way to go is up.
Looking at Animal Cruelty Through the Lens of Child Labor in U.S. History
I believe that the market exploits animals much like it did child laborers through the reasoning of profit and market dynamics. Children workers in the U.S. were generally treated as legal non-entities until the Fair Labor Standards Act was created which defended them from labor-exploitation. Although children are not farmed animals, I believe that their similarity lies in their economic exploitation, their “lack of legal standing” and shared suffering. The pre-child labor laws market exploited children and denied them their health and humanity because it was profitable and legal, just as the current market exploits animals and denies them their sentience for the same reasons. Federal regulations for animal cruelty can be fought alongside rules for agricultural pollution, worker’s rights, and our health; much like children's labor rights were fought alongside rights for other working peoples. Much like the Fair Labor Standards Act, a federal law defining and enforcing rules regarding animal cruelty would shut down modern CAFO’s in favor of more ethical animal farming practices that respect animal sentience, and the effects of animal agriculture on our environment.
SOURCES:
http://www.continuetolearn.uiowa.edu/laborctr/child_labor/about/us_history.html
http://www.continuetolearn.uiowa.edu/laborctr/child_labor/about/causes.html
Causes of Our Unethical Treatment of Farm Animals
What Singer and Mason could have clearly stated in their book that would support their effort to expose what’s wrong with the way American factory farms operate is that our capitalist economic system is at the root of the environmental, health, and animal welfare problems that factory farms create. The need to outcompete other meat production businesses and the need for money that capitalism creates are the causes of farm workers becoming “desensitized” to animal suffering and ignoring any innate ethical tendencies they may have to treat animals kindly. These same drives produced by capitalism are what possess farm workers to use environmentally harmful chemicals (e.g., pesticides) that can help increase crop productivity.
Even if we didn’t abolish capitalism or alter the way it functions in our society, we could at least follow Europe’s example by implementing stricter regulations that ban artificial hormones and antibiotics that pose risks to human, animal, and environmental health. Singer and Mason do devote much of their book to discussing the implications of market competition on animal welfare and the environment and the tighter regulations that exist in Europe, but specifically defining solutions to these current problems associated with factory farming would have strengthened their analysis.
The lies on egg cartons!
Singer will only be happy if Humans convert to veganism
Singer asks for an inch only to take a mile. One can only ask what he will demand next. It shouldn’t be hard to imagine that if Singer was to be successful in restricting all meat production to come solely from free-range farming techniques that he would press for complete turnover to vegetarian and vegan food choices. Singer’s quick transition to vegetarianism will be met with a great deal of resistance; however, if he slowly attacked the industry, his radical ideas may become reality. Singer inadvertently has belittled all progress in the industry, and if I was a mass producing farmer I would refuse to partake in the transition. Singer may refute this argument by saying that the consumers choose the trend not the farmers, and will do so by choosing the product that they wish to put on their tables. As this is true with higher end families, those that shop for deals and for easy availability may never move away from mass produced meats.
Sunday, November 8, 2009
On page 47 they give the example of the inhuman treatment animals in zoo’s once had to endure. What changed those practices was the outcry from the Zoo’s patrons. This seems to suggest hearing about the atrocities of animal cruelty isn’t enough; rather people need to see and more importantly feel something in order for them to act. Who can care about a chicken though? We care more about dogs in this country because of the human qualities they possess. We can see and feel when they are happy or sad, but when it comes to chickens their mental state never enters our mind. This mainly occurs because they are out of our mind, on the whole we never interact with these animals and therefore have almost no inclination to view them as having value other than the value we get in eating them. So it seems that as human consumers we respond mostly to what evokes emotion. How can animal rights groups achieve this on a large enough scale? Although the authors don’t say this explicitly I wonder if they discount a free market approach all together. This leads me to the second question that consumed me through out. The authors seem to demonize the free market for the corporate greed it produces but don’t really think twice about the change it can bring about in consumer trends.
On page 75 the authors note an example which serves to answer in some way my question of the role the free market could play in curbing or changing consumer trends. The example of McDonald’s veggie burger being better for the consumer and the environment suggests that there is room for the market to help improve the environment. Erika Frank, a professor at Emory, says the McVeggie burger tastes similar to the regular burger at McDonalds. While I doubt this is actually true, what if McDonalds was to improve the taste of this burger. If people started buying this burger after seeing that it was better for their health and the environment on top of it tasting the same as the regular burger this would force other chains create a similar burger. This may result in an improved environment while utilizing consumer trends instead of trying to combat them!